NOTE: This post is
rated R for mild strong language.
Introduction
You might not actually care if cyclists use the word “kit”
to mean “those silly Lycra clothes we bikers wear.” Frankly, I don’t much care myself. But I do care how we approach language in
general; how we choose the words we use; and what impact we can have on how the
vernacular evolves. If you love
language—and don’t like it eroded by indiscriminate usage—then you should read this
post. It’s the third installment in a
series about “kit,” and you can read the first installment here and the second here.
In this essay I rebut an argument from my friend W—, which you
haven’t read. Yeah, I know that’s
awkward, but I don’t wish to quote W—’s entire e-mail. So I’ll quote his most salient points, college-paper
style. If nothing else you’ll get a nice
crash course here in identifying logical fallacies.
Straw man
W— begins his argument by stating, “Your whole argument
boils down to this: ‘I don’t like Cool Hunting and the things they promote on
their website; therefore, use of the word “kit” to mean cycling clothing is
invalid.’”
This is a blatant example of what is called the “straw man”
fallacy. This argumentative technique
involves erecting an inferior version of your opponent’s argument that can be
easily knocked down. Straw man fallacies
can be effective, particularly when the audience doesn’t have the original
argument at hand. I’ll save you the
trouble of looking at my earlier posts:
here is a distillation of what I wrote.
- When we use a word, we participate in all its connotations whether we like it or not.
- Using a word can subtly pressure others to adopt it; one teammate admitted, “‘Kit’ still sounds dumb to me, but I use the word because I think I am supposed to.”
- Perhaps “kit” is useful, but we can avoid sounding like wannabe Euro types by using a different term.
- “Costume” is a better word for bike clothing, because so many of us cyclists are poseurs. By using a term that mocks our own pretentiousness, we beat others to the punch.
The above points are from my first post. That is, I made them before W— even
pointed out to me that the website Cool Hunting uses the term “kit.” How could my whole argument boil down to my
reaction to a website I hadn’t yet seen when I made it?
In my second post, I made these points:
- Cool Hunting’s use of the term “kit” does not, in my opinion, validate the word whatsoever.
- Word choice is a matter not just of utility but of taste. The members of my bike club avoid “bidon,” despite knowing what it means, because we don’t like it. That “bidon” has a following doesn’t sway us.
- The elasticity of language and the basic ability of a word to convey meaning should not be trotted out as blanket justifications for adopting new usage.
- There is ample precedent for refusing to adopt popular expressions (e.g., “at the end of the day,” “step up our game,” “swing for the fences,” “incent”).
W—’s argument is a straw man fallacy because he has falsely
claimed that one of my points is representative of all the others. It simply isn’t.
Meanwhile, W— hasn’t even represented my argument correctly
as regards Cool Hunting. I didn’t say
Cool Hunting’s use of “kit” is invalid; I simply said that Cool Hunting’s use
of “kit” doesn’t, by itself, validate widespread adoption of the word. That is, I’m not going to start using “kit”
just because some website does, especially when it’s a dorky website selling
needless, overpriced, twee crap to hipsters.
W— either misunderstood what I meant by “validate,” or he’s quibbling.
Allow me to further clarify my position on “valid” vs.
“validate.” Here’s an analogy. In the South, people often
say “y’all.” I find this a highly useful
(i.e., valid) term, because it’s the only plural sense of “you” that exists in
English. However, the meaning it conveys
is perhaps insufficient to validate my own use of the term, because “y’all” is
not typical Californian vernacular and my use of it can be puzzling to people. (I sometimes can’t resist its utility; this
has caused others to think I was from the South or was pretending to be.)
By the way, there’s something you should know about Cool
Hunting (this isn’t part of my argument, but is just a warning):
The red herring
fallacy
Three paragraphs of W—’s e-mail pertain to arguments against
“kit” advanced by our teammate Trevor, who started this ball rolling by
questioning my use of “kit.” Trevor
attacks the notion that this term is specific and clear enough to be valid. This is an entirely separate argument from
mine, and for W— to respond to Trevor’s argument (in an e-mail addressed to me)
is to commit a “red herring” fallacy. When he writes, “Remember, the argument is not about what words you like or don’t like to use, it is about the correctness of the term ‘kit’ to refer to cycling clothing,” he’s refuting the wrong argument. My argument has always been about whether or not we ought to support “kit.” I’ve gone after its connotations, not its value as a conveyer of meaning.
As you probably already know, a red herring is an argument
that seems reasonable, but doesn’t actually address your opponent’s argument. (In my household it’s known as “red lobster”
because my young daughter once goofed when rattling off a list of logical
fallacies.) A red herring can be an
intentional effort to distract the audience from the subject, or an
unintentional loss of focus. W—’s red
herring is a slide toward straw man, as it conflates Trevor’s argument with
mine.
Here’s an analogy.
Suppose both my kids hate spinach.
Suppose Lindsay says, “Spinach is gross because it’s slimy.” And suppose Alexa says, “I hate spinach
because it tastes like shit.” To say,
“Alexa, you’re forgetting that uncooked spinach on a salad is quite crisp” is
to attack the wrong argument, conveniently ignoring what Alexa actually said. (Take note:
I find “tastes like shit” to be a powerful and valid phrase, but not one
that I’d allow my kids to actually use. Again,
utility is not the only criterion by which to judge linguistic choices.)
W— invokes another red herring when he links to this article about the
origin of the word “bike,” joking that there may have been “some bike club back
in 1882 or so whose riders had a raging argument about how ‘impossibly stupid’
and ‘twee’-sounding it was to refer to a bicycle as a ‘bike.’” But the article he cites doesn’t concern any
objection to “bike,” certainly not on the grounds that it was affectation of
any kind. If the British had adopted
“bike” many years before Americans, and those Americans who adopted it also
used silly words like “bidon,” maybe W— would be getting somewhere. But “bike,” according to the article, is an
Americanism.
Argumentum ad populum
W— contends that “it is correct, normal—and in fact quite
common, even among non-Kiwi, non-Brit, non-Euro English speakers—to use the
term kit to refer to a cycling jersey and shorts. None of your criticism of
Cool Hunting refutes that. And in fact their usage serves as proof that even a
non-cycling specific website with national/international reach uses the term in
the way I describe.” W— goes on to
describe a survey he did among participants in the Port of Oakland ride, asking
what they call bike clothing. The
result: “8 out of 10 serious responses
were ‘kit.’ These are real, living users
of the English language.” (I wonder if
it’s really fair to throw out non-serious responses; after all, isn’t the court
jester typically the voice of reason in Shakespeare? And “real, living users” somehow makes me
think of the signs outside strip clubs saying, “See and talk to live nude
girls!” Is this parenthetical aside a
red herring? Absolutely. Will the phrase “nude girls” bring traffic to
my blog? I hope so.)
An argumentum ad
populum fallacy is made when the popularity of an idea is represented as evidence
of the legitimacy or veracity of that idea.
Sometimes it’s tempting to assume something is right simply because so
many people believe that it is. (Here’s
a doozy of an argumentum ad populum: “Cigarettes are great! After all, 40 million Americans can’t be
wrong!”)
Whether W— commits this fallacy hinges on what he means by
“correct” where word choice is concerned. So I’ll quote him again; he reiterates that
“kit” is “correct English usage, in common parlance in the USA, at least among
bikies.” So for him, “correct” means “in
common use,” and I hope I don’t commit my own straw man fallacy by paraphrasing
his argument thus: “People do call it ‘kit.’ Get over it.”
So, his “everybody’s doing it” argument works okay if you
construe proper usage as “talking the way everybody else talks.” If we accept “conveys
meaning” as the be-all and end-all of language, then W— isn’t really committing
a fallacy here. But of course we
shouldn’t accept “conveys meaning” as the true calling of language. That’s where the next fallacy comes in.
Naturalistic fallacy
and the is/ought problem
The Scottish philosopher David Hume wrote, in A Treatise on Human Nature, “I have
always remarked, that the author proceeds for some time in the ordinary way of
reasoning, and establishes the being of a god, or makes observations concerning
human affairs; when of a sudden I am surprised to find that instead of the
usual copulations of proposition, is and
is not, I meet with no proposition
that is not connected with an ought or
ought not.”
Building on this, the British philosopher G.E. Moore
introduced the term “naturalistic fallacy” and warned against drawing moral or
qualitative judgments—the ought—from
empirical observation—the is. Notions like Social Darwinism, the validity
of unrestrained capitalism, eugenics, Ayn Rand’s Objectivism, and so forth are all committing the naturalistic fallacy. This fallacy lurks behind many a defeatist
approach, such as, “If the great grey owl can’t handle a little habitat
displacement, maybe it just wasn’t meant to be.
Fate favors pigeons. Get over it.”
As language goes, the naturalistic fallacy promotes the assumption
that the way words end up being used is the same thing as how words ought to be used. So a
person may reason, “If enough people call a lectern a podium, well, I can too! If teenagers are throwing around
words like ‘twerk’ and ‘vape,’ well, maybe I should too, to show how youthful
and with-it I am! And, I can always use ‘their’
as a third-person singular possessive pronoun (e.g., ‘each person must have
their own ticket’), since everybody else does it. It has become correct, by definition!” Okay, fine, talk like that. But don’t assume everybody’s going to like
it, or that everybody should.
What does this have to do with “kit”? Well, W— keeps pointing out examples of how
“kit” is used. I’m trying to make the case that perhaps it ought not be used. Not because “kit” is as foul as “YOLO” or “artisanal,”
but because I think we (i.e., my bike club, and the readers of this blog) can
do better.
The do-gooder problem
As for as I know, “the do-gooder problem” isn’t an
established category of problem, like a logical fallacy is.
But I feel the need to address a whiff of egalitarian, all-together-now
spirit in W—’s argument: again and
again, he equates “correct” with “normal” and “common.” Thus,
when a person like me seeks to fault all these good, common, honest people who
are just gettin’ it said, the only way they know how ... well, this may come
off as elitist.
To combat the possible PR issue here, I’d like to make a
distinction between “elite” and “elitist.”
In my opinion, the desire to do something really well (i.e., better than
the average person does) doesn’t make you elitist. It may make you elite (if you’re successful),
but being elite is not itself being elitist and is not a character flaw.
You know that viral YouTube video “Shit Cyclists Say”? I won’t lie—I’ve heard a lot of those
lines from my teammates and I’ve used a few myself—but our general level of
discourse is much higher than this. During
bike rides, I’ve had fascinating discussions about economics, public key
encryption, net neutrality, glaciers, human nature, and—yes—language. We don’t judge—though we may debate—and we
set a high standard for one another.
This high standard comes through in our members’ race reports, which are consistently funny,
food-centric, and well-written. One member
even took a page from the celebrity playbook and enlisted a ghost writer
to help burnish his report. Even
something as basic as the name of our training race has been subject to continual
revision: “Hammer Ride” became “Haimer
Ride” (based on an e-mail typo) before being renamed “House of Pain” which
(perhaps because it wasn’t original, or perhaps because it was too brash) was
changed to “Domicile of Hurt” (the acronym being implicit). This still wasn’t good enough so it was then changed
to the delightfully redundant “Domicile of Yurt.” It’s this spirit of constant innovation that
makes me think we EBVCers (and you, elite reader of blogs) could be leaders in the
linguistic realm instead of blithely adopting whatever trendy lingo we come
across.
So, to reiterate:
“kit” is a valid term, perhaps not completely precise but nonetheless
useful (unlike “irregardless” and “biweekly”).
I don’t care who uses “kit,” and I won’t call you out for using it, and I
plan to use it myself from time to time as a safeguard against dogmatism
(though anybody who knows me will automatically fill in the air quotes, like he
or she presumably does every time I insert a pregnant pause before uttering the
word “Internet”). But, recognizing that we can choose to accept or deflect memes, I
encourage you to second-guess “kit.” Sure,
it’s a word; sure, it’s valid—but is that really enough?
No comments:
Post a Comment